The death penalty must go, for it obliterates a distinction fundamental to our existence

Gautam Patel, Mumbai Mirror

In the face of unspeakable horror, resisting what must have been the strongest temptation to lash out, the tone of the Supreme Court’s decision in the Qasab case is calm, gentleandalwaysjudicious.Thereis,too,an uncommon grace and breadth of mind: the decision ends with six paragraphs that are in themselves unusual. The Supreme Court thanks appearing counsel, and makes special mention of the exemplary work of the trial court judge, Justice M L Tahaliyani (now a judge of the Bombay High Court).
This calmness is at odds with the matter at hand.ItishardtothinkoftheQasabcasewithout being driven to instant, unthinking rage: pictures of the blood-smeared floor of the CST train station, of Qasab dressed like a college student but armed to the teeth, and, above all, his apparent complete indifference to what he was doing. The immediate reaction therefore is, always: hanghim.Suggesttheabolitionofthedeathpenalty and the common response is, yes, fine; but only after we hang Qasab.
Should we? Should we hang anybody? Should the law permit this? In an article here in March,Iarguedthatitistimeforthedeathpenalty to go because, apart from anything else, it is both error-prone and irreversible. In July, 14 former judges of the Supreme Court and our High CourtswrotetothePresidentaskingthathecommute to life imprisonment the death sentences of13convicts.TheappealdoesnotseektheabolitionoftheDP,whateverthepersonalviewsofsignatories. It points, instead, to the significant errors and mistakes in administering this law, and to the Supreme Court’s own admission that it went wrong in several DP cases. Specifically, that the standard set by the Supreme Court in Bachan Singh’scaseof1980–thattheDPistheexception tothegeneralruleoflifeimprisonmentasamaximum sentence; that the DP should be imposed only in the “rarest of rare” cases; and that in imposing it, courts should look at both crime and criminal — was upended in a later case, Ravji (1996), decided by a bench of fewer judges, which said it is the gravity of the crime that is determinative, not the criminal; and that subsequentcasesincorrectlyfollowedRavji.Theresult wasanincorrectapplicationofthelawandtheerroneous sentencing to death of many. That mistake was discovered only in 2009 in yet another case, Bariyar, too late to save two men, wrongly hanged by the law.
This“rarestofrare”standardispuzzling.Itadmits of no absolute or objective measure. What is raretoonemightbecommontoanother.Twoorders from the extremities of the judicial pyramid show how uneven this standard is. A few days after the Qasab decision, a special court in Ahmedabad convicted Maya Kodnani and Babu Bajrangi and sentenced them to long terms of imprisonment for their role in the massacres at Naroda Patiya during the 2002 Gujarat riots. Both have been convicted, among other things, ofmurder.BetweenQasab,whoarrivedasanoutsiderandmassacredpeoplehedidnotknow,and Kodnani and Bajrangi who turned on their own townspeople in ways equally horrific, why is one “rare” and the other not? In the Gujarat riots cases lies yet another contradiction: many of those convicted of the Godhra train massacre received death sentences. Was Godhra rare, but Naroda Patiya not? What nice points of distinction enable us to decide who dies and who lives?
Two of the signatories to the appeal to the President, Justice Ganguly and Justice AP Shah, have in separate interviews expressed their personal views in favour of abolishing the DP. Both make compelling arguments. “The legal safeguards aimed at avoiding a miscarriage of capital punishment have failed to deliver,” says Justice Shah. “I cannot say today that the death penalty isunconstitutional,butfreakishandrandomimposition of the death penalty is certainly unconstitutional,” is Justice Ganguly’s view.
Many writers (including Yug Mohit Chaudhry, the Bombay High Court lawyer who initiatedtheappealtothePresidentandamanofferocious tenacity) have explained at length why it must go: personal predilections, prejudice and bias, and individualistic aberrations show that the DP is inherently unreliable. Justice John Paul Stevens of the US Supreme Court reversed course after 32 years, arguing that “the death penalty represents ‘the pointless and needless extinction of life with only marginal contributions to any discernible social or public purposes’“. Philosophers, writers and leaders, too, have weighed in. “Capital punishment is the most premeditated of murders,” said Albert Camus, and Desmond Tutu felt that “to take a life when a life has been lost is revenge, not justice”.
But perhaps the most striking indictment of capital punishment comes from those to whom it falls to oversee its administration; people like Lewis Lawes, the warden of New York’s Sing Sing prison in the 1920s and 30s: “As if one crime of such nature, done by a single man, acting individually, can be expiated by a similar crime done by all men, acting collectively.”
The death penalty must go, for it obliterates a distinction fundamental to our existence: the distinction between revenge and justice, between being primitive and being civilized, between being human and being inhuman.